School of Computing. Dublin City University.
Online coding site: Ancient Brain
coders JavaScript worlds
reward: if (good event) r else swhere r > s.
Proof: Let us fix r and s and learn the Q-values. In a deterministic world, given a state x, the Q-value for action a will be:
for some real numbers . The Q-value for a different action b will be:
where . That is, e + f = c + d .
So whichever one of c and e is bigger defines which is the best action (which gets the larger amount of the "good" reward r), irrespective of the sizes of r > s.
To be precise, if c > e, then Q(x,a) > Q(x,b)
Note that these numbers are not integers - it may not be simply a question of the worse action receiving s instead of r a finite number of times. The worse action may also receive r instead of s at some points, and also the number of differences may in fact not be finite.
To be precise, noting that (c-e) = (f-d) , the difference between the Q-values is:
where the real number (c-e) is constant for the given two actions a and b in state x. (c-e) depends only on the probabilities of events happening, not on the specific values of the rewards r and s that we hand out when they do. Changing the relative sizes of the rewards r > s can only change the magnitude of the difference between the Q-values, but not the sign. The ranking of actions will stay the same.
For example, an agent with rewards (10,9) and an agent with rewards (10,0) will have different Q-values but will still suggest the same optimal action .
In a probabilistic world, we would have:
where p + q = 1 , and:
for some p' + q' = 1 .
I think this should just read:
E(rt+1) | = Σ y Pxa(y) r(x,y) |
= Pxa(y1) r(x,y1) + ... + Pxa(yn) r(x,yn) | |
= p' r + q' s |
Hence:
for some as before.
Proof: From the proof of Theorem C.1:
where is a constant independent of the particular rewards.
Using our "deviation" definition, for the 2-reward agent in a deterministic world:
The size of the W-value that presents in state x if is the leader is simply proportional to the difference between its rewards. If wants to take the same action as , then (that is, (c-e) = 0). If the leader switches to , the constant switches to .
Increasing the difference between its rewards will cause to have the same disagreements with the other agents about what action to take, but higher values - that is, an increased ability to compete. So the progress of the W-competition will be different.
For example, an agent with rewards (8,5) will be stronger (will have higher W-values and win more competitions) than an agent with the same logic and rewards (2,0). And an agent with rewards (2,0) will be stronger than one with rewards (10,9). In particular, the strongest possible 2-reward agent is:
reward: if (good event) else
reward: if (good event) (r-s) else 0From Theorem C.1, this will have different Q-values but the same Q-learning policy. And from Theorem C.2, it will have identical W-values. You can regard the original agent as an (r-s), 0 agent which also picks up an automatic bonus of s every step no matter what it does. Its Q-values can be obtained by simply adding the following to each of the Q-values of the (r-s), 0 agent:
We are shifting the same contour up and down the y-axis in Figure 8.1.
The same suggested action and the same W-values means that for the purposes of W-learning it is the same agent. For example, an agent with rewards (1.5,1.1) is identical in W-learning to one with rewards (0.4,0). The W=Q method would treat them differently.
reward: if (good event) r else 0where r > 0 .
Proof: We have just multiplied all rewards by c, so all Q-values are multiplied by c. If this is not clear, see the general proof Theorem D.1.
I should note this only works if: c > 0
will have the same policy as ,
but different W-values.
We are exaggerating or levelling out the contour
in Figure 8.1.
In particular, the strongest possible normalised agent is:
reward: if (good event) else 0
Return to Contents page.